Campbell, in my view rightly, rejects the proposed
dichotomy between two kinds of grounding. I’d be inclined to say: to think of grammar
and of human nature as somehow offering parallel modalities – each setting its
own kind of limit to what is possible in moral thought – is confused. Indeed, I’m
not even clear what it would be to think of the two sentences above, taken in
isolation, as expressing either an empirical claim or a point of grammar. Deciding
whether someone loves evil (or cow dung) is not like establishing whether someone
is allergic to fish roe. For one thing, the terms of the relation, “fish roe” and
“allergy” are distinct. But love and its object cannot in this way be thought of
separately. How love is expressed, what it demands of us, is dependent on the object
of love. To show my love of someone is to show my understanding of her.
It is also unclear under
what aspect a person might be taken to love evil. Does he love evil for its
own sake (e.g. a sadist, a person embittered by life, someone in the grip of vindictiveness,
etc), or for what he hopes it will bring (e.g. a terrorist)?
For another thing, and connected with this, we are acquainted
with the kinds of context in which food allergies are spoken about, the reasons
for being concerned about it, the practical consequences. But when the philosopher
raises the question whether it is possible or impossible to love evil, there is
no context enabling us to get clear about the nature of the relation being considered.
*
What about the
notion that morality might be grounded in grammar? How are we to think of the
idea that the wrongness of an action is part of the very concept of the action
(is internal to its description)? Would that mean that someone who murders an
innocent human being or who lies to a friend is in violation of grammar or in
the grip of a grammatical confusion?
Campbell quotes Cora
Diamond’s “Eating Meat and Eating People”:
Well, there might be circumstances in which a person would find herself reduced to eating her dog, for instance, to fend off imminent starvation. So perhaps we might reformulate the point as follows: to think of an animal as a pet is not to think of it as food - though the fact that a person will eat something in a dire situation, or, say, as part of a ritual, does not entail that she thinks of it as food.[T]here are some actions. . . that are part of the way we come to understand and indicate our recognition of what kind it is with which we are concerned. [. . .] [I]t is not “morally wrong” to eat our pets; people who ate their pets would not have pets in the same sense of the term. (C. Diamond, The Realistic Spirit, MIT Press, 1991, p. 323.)
Would the realization that
if I thought of my dog as food I would not regard it as a pet in the same sense
as others do somehow keep me from eating it? Why should it? I might simply
shrug my shoulders and say to myself: “All right, so my dog isn’t a pet in that sense.” The fact
that we don’t think of pets as food is bound up with the fact that we aren’t tempted to eat them, indeed we normally
have a revulsion to eating them. In that sense, not regarding pets as food is
not a “mere convention”, notwithstanding the fact that customs concerning what
kinds of animal are food vary between cultures. (In China, for instance, the attitude
towards eating dog meat is different: there is a movement afoot there to discourage
the eating of dogs and cats. In this connection, one may need to distinguish between
eating certain species of animals often kept as pets, and eating one’s own
pets.)
Now could we imagine people
who shared our attitudes to pets in most respects, but regarded them as food? First,
we should recall that “our” attitude to pets vary greatly: pets are a varied
category (the Swedish category husdjur even
more so), and so is the category of pet owner: not every dog owner has his dog
sign Christmas cards or brings flowers to his cat’s grave each year on the date
of her death. Anyway, if there is a conflict between regarding an animal as
food and having towards it the other attitudes that go with regarding an animal
as a pet, the conflict is of a psychological kind; a matter of “human nature”.
This by itself entails nothing as to the way pets should be treated.
Could we, on the other
hand, imagine a society lacking anything corresponding to our concept of a pet?
Without difficulty: though of course, life in that society would differ
markedly from ours in several respects.