The Nordic Wittgenstein Review has published a new issue: Vol. 4, No. 2,
(2015). It is available Open Access, i.e. free of charge, online, for
anyone to read. See below.
Peaceful holidays to those who have them!
Best wishes,
Yrsa, and the Editors Martin and Anne-Marie
PS. CFP - Online submission by January 31, 2016
________
NORDIC WITTGENSTEIN REVIEW 4 (2) 2015
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/issue/current
Note from the Editors
Yrsa Neuman, Anne-Marie Søndergaard Christensen, Martin Gustafsson
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3399/pdf
INVITED PAPER
Naturalism, Conventionalism, and Forms of Life: Wittgenstein and the
"Cratylus"
Paul M Livingston
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3399/pdf
ARTICLES
Reincarnation and the Lack of Imagination in Philosophy
Mikel Burley
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3281/pdf
A Missing Folio at the Beginning of Wittgenstein's MS 104
Martin Pilch
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3300/pdf
"Let us imagine...": Wittgenstein's Invitation to Philosophy
Beth Savickey
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3292/pdf
FROM THE ARCHIVES
On the Ketner and Eigsti Edition of Wittgenstein’s Remarks on Frazer’s
"The Golden Bough"
Peter K. Westergaard
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3280/pdf
BOOK REVIEWS
Wittgenstein’s Lecture on Ethics, edited by Zamuner, Di Lascio & Levy
Lars Hertzberg
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3395/pdf
Some Thoughts on "Varieties of Skepticism" by James Conant and Andrea
Kern (eds.)
Adam Leite
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3397/pdf
Review of "Clarity and Confusion in Social Theory" by Leonidas Tsilipakos
Robert Vinten
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3391/pdf
December 27, 2015
December 19, 2015
Jon Fosse between the language games
I recently had occasion to watch the play Barnet [The child] by Norwegian
playwright Jon Fosse at the Dramaten Theatre in Stockholm. It was a moving
experience; the dialogue moves slowly and undramatically, the surface is calm
but strong emotions move underneath: dread, love, compassion. Speakers
communicate not so much through the specific things said, the words used, as
through the way they speak, or through the mere fact of saying something.
The dialogue has a ring of Beckett or
Pinter, but in Fosse’s play the words are closer to actual everyday
conversation. He appears to have an ability to listen to the way we actually
talk free from preconceptions about what linguistic communication is. (Fosse also
seems to view his characters with more sympathy than Beckett and Pinter do.)
The
play is about a man, Fredrick, and a woman, Agnes, who meet, fall in love and
move in together. She becomes pregnant, there are complications, she is taken to
hospital, tests have to be made to determine whether labour will have to be
induced prematurely, which would entail a grave risk for the survival of the
child.
Here
is a conversation between Fredrick and a nurse waiting for the test results:
FREDRICK
(Questioning)
Does
something like this happen often
NURSE
It
seems so anyway
FREDRICK
Because
it’s things like this they work
on
here
NURSE
Yes
FREDRICK
Yes
it’s like that I guess
(Pause)
But
won’t she come soon
NURSE
(Looks at her watch)
Yes
she’ll probably come
soon
now
FREDRICK
(Troubled)
Is
it taking a longer time than usual
NURSE
(Draws it out)
No
FREDRICK
(Looks at her sceptically)
Are
you certain
NURSE
Maybe
it’s taken a little longer
It’s
taken a bit of time
(Short pause)
But
that isn’t unusual
These
examinations
can
often take time
You
know
the
doctors are often busy
FREDRICK
I
know
NURSE
But
tonight
it’s
been quiet so far
She’ll
probably come soon
(The quotation is from Jon Fosse, Plays One, London: Oberon Books, 2002,
pp. 265 f. The translation is by Louis Muinzer. It may be noticed that the
lines do not have punctuation marks.)
If
one were to try to understand what the characters are saying as an attempt at acquiring
and conveying information it would all seem hopelessly bewildered. What exactly
would it mean for “something like this” to happen “often” or not so “often”?
How often is “often”, how soon is “soon”? Does the nurse have any concrete
grounds for saying that Agnes will be back soon? She offers an explanation of
why the process might take longer (“the doctors are often busy”) but
immediately takes it back (“tonight it’s been quiet so far”).
(There’s
the same kind of ambivalence in the doctor telling Fredrick to prepare for the
worst yet keep his hopes up:
It can be all right
this sort of thing
But
well to be frank
the chances aren’t
so great)
Fredrick’s
questions seek reassurance rather than information, and the nurse tries to
offer it. Their remarks have something of the character of poetry or song. The
dialogue brings to mind Wittgenstein’s remark (Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. I, § 888):
The way music
speaks. Don’t forget that even though a poem is framed in the language of
information, it is not employed in the language game of information….
Verbal language contains a strong
musical element. (A sigh, the modulation of tone for a question, for an
announcement, for longing; all the countless gestures in the verbal
cadences.)
One could imagine a culture in which,
rather than ask and answer questions, the participants in this kind of
interaction played pieces of music for one another, or together. Of course, what they played would vary with the
situation.
¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨
The interest of this, to me, is that Fosse
brings to the fore aspects of human conversation that tend to be overlooked in
accounts of language and meaning.
Paul
Grice, famously, defined speaker’s meaning as follows:
“A meantNN
something by x” is (roughly) equivalent to “A intended the utterance of x
to produce some effect in an audience by means of the recognition of this
intention; and we may add that to ask what A meant is to ask for a
specification of the intended effect. (“Meaning”, originally in Philosophical Review 66 (1957))
(“MeaningNN” – “nonnatural
meaning” - stands for cases in which somebody means this or that by something, as opposed to cases of
“natural” – i.e. roughly causal meaning – as when we say “These spots mean
measles”.)
One
type of case Grice considers is “an utterance [which], if it qualifies at all
as meaningNN something, will be of a descriptive or informative
kind”, in which case the attitude to be produced “will be a cognitive one, for
example, a belief.” When the nurse says, “she’ll probably come soon now”, then,
is she attempting to produce a certain belief (which belief exactly?) in
Fredrick? But even if we take it that that is not what she is doing, can we
really understand her words except through reference to the practice of
conveying information? Her words are “framed in the language of information”
(and that’s what enables us to understand them) but they are not “employed in
the language game of information” (nor do we take them to be).
Similarly,
we might ask: in Searlian terms, what is the illocutionary force of the nurse’s
lines? Are they assertives, thus counting “as an undertaking to the effect that
[the proposition uttered] represents an actual state of affairs”?
¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨
J. L. Austin was impressively sensitive to
word nuances, not so much to the kinds of speakings there are. Philosophers of
language like Grice, Austin or Searle are apt to look at the variety of human
forms of linguistic interaction through a grid pattern imposed, I believe, by a
tendency to model speech on written language – or perhaps we should say: on the
kind of language we were taught to produce at school, with complete and
grammatically consistent subject-predicate sentences and clearly indicated
references, each sentence having been constructed for a distinct purpose. (For
an exception, see Charles Taylor on the expressive use of speech, “Theories of
Meaning”, in his collection Human Agency
and Language.)
When M. Jourdain
in Molière’s The Bourgeois Gentleman is
told that unknowingly he has been speaking prose all his life I am not so sure
that was accurate. The idea of written prose shapes our ways of looking at
speech, it influences the way we actually speak in various contexts, but many
of our interchanges are no closer to written prose than they are to poetry.
We
are all familiar with conversations like that quoted above, yet philosophers are
inclined to ignore them in thinking about language. The speakers’ lines have an
obvious role in the interchange. We can well imagine the sort of line that
would be out of place in the context. Yet the words are not used instrumentally
in the sense of being deliberately chosen with a specific aim in mind.
¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨
Wittgenstein writes, in Philosophical Investigations, Part II
ix:
79. ---- Is it
so surprising that I use the same expression in different games? And sometimes,
as it were, even in between the games?
80. And do I
always talk with very definite purpose? – And is what I say senseless because I
don’t?
A playwright like Jon Fosse can make us notice
what lies between the language games.
October 06, 2015
NORDIC WITTGENSTEIN REVIEW, Special issue on Wittgenstein and forms of life
The Nordic Wittgenstein Review, published by the NWS, has published its
first ever Special Issue, edited by Danièle Moyal-Sharrock, Piergiorgio
Donatelli and Sandra Laugier in collaboration with the present editors
of NWR.
It's open access, as always.
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/issue/view/NWR%20Special%20Issue%202015
Best wishes,
Yrsa Neuman as the ed-in-chief
Anne-Marie Soendergaard Christensen & Martin Gustafsson, editors
PS. Submissions to NWR:
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/about/submissions#onlineSubmissions
---
PLEASE DO CIRCULATE
Note from the Editors
Daniele Moyal-Sharrock 0
Forms of Life
Peter Hacker 1-20
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3320/pdf
Wittgenstein on Forms of Life, Patterns of Life, and Ways of Living
Daniele Moyal-Sharrock 21-42
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3362/pdf
Forms of Life, Forms of Reality
Piergiorgio Donatelli 43-62
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3374/pdf
Voice as Form of Life and Life Form
Sandra Laugier 63-82
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3364/pdf
Tractarian Form as the Precursor to Forms of Life
Chon Tejedor 83-109
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3358/pdf
Mathematics and Forms of Life
Severin Schroeder 111-130
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3357/pdf
“If Some People Looked Like Elephants and Others Like Cats”:
Wittgenstein on Understanding Others and Forms of Life
Constantine Sandis 131-153
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3372/pdf
Elucidating Forms of Life. The Evolution of a Philosophical Tool
Anna Boncompagni 155-175
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3319/pdf
first ever Special Issue, edited by Danièle Moyal-Sharrock, Piergiorgio
Donatelli and Sandra Laugier in collaboration with the present editors
of NWR.
It's open access, as always.
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/issue/view/NWR%20Special%20Issue%202015
Best wishes,
Yrsa Neuman as the ed-in-chief
Anne-Marie Soendergaard Christensen & Martin Gustafsson, editors
PS. Submissions to NWR:
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/about/submissions#onlineSubmissions
---
PLEASE DO CIRCULATE
Note from the Editors
Daniele Moyal-Sharrock 0
Forms of Life
Peter Hacker 1-20
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3320/pdf
Wittgenstein on Forms of Life, Patterns of Life, and Ways of Living
Daniele Moyal-Sharrock 21-42
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3362/pdf
Forms of Life, Forms of Reality
Piergiorgio Donatelli 43-62
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3374/pdf
Voice as Form of Life and Life Form
Sandra Laugier 63-82
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3364/pdf
Tractarian Form as the Precursor to Forms of Life
Chon Tejedor 83-109
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3358/pdf
Mathematics and Forms of Life
Severin Schroeder 111-130
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3357/pdf
“If Some People Looked Like Elephants and Others Like Cats”:
Wittgenstein on Understanding Others and Forms of Life
Constantine Sandis 131-153
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3372/pdf
Elucidating Forms of Life. The Evolution of a Philosophical Tool
Anna Boncompagni 155-175
http://www.nordicwittgensteinreview.com/article/view/3319/pdf
September 15, 2015
Recent doctoral dissertations at Åbo Akademi
Recent doctoral dissertations at Åbo Akademi
During the last academic year three doctoral dissertations in philosophy were defended at my old department at Åbo Akademi, Åbo/Turku, Finland:
Ylva Gustafsson, Interpersonal understanding
and theory of mind (19 September, 2014)
Summary: The claim that a “theory of mind”,
is a fundamental cognitive capacity that grounds human social life is popular
within both modern philosophical and psychological theorising on interpersonal
understanding. This claim surfaces in evolutionary psychology, in theories of
child development, in theories of autism as well as in philosophy on emotions
and in moral philosophy. The aim of this work is to scrutinise certain
psychological and philosophical theories on interpersonal understanding that
are connected with empirical research. The author argues that the theories as
well as the empirical research are often based on problematic philosophical
assumptions about interpersonal understanding. The assumptions shape the
theories and also shape the way empirical research is designed and the way results are
interpreted.
For the full text, see https://www.doria.fi/handle/10024/98819
¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨
Antony Fredriksson, Vision, Image,
Record – A Cultivation of the Visual Field (9 January, 2015)
Summary: The first part of
this thesis delivers a genealogy of the image.
It chronicles how the concepts of image, vision and the self evolved in
relation to one another in a specific scientific and philosophical context,
starting with the early Renaissance, which saw the invention of the
perspectivist painting, up to the birth of Positivism and the photographic
image. This development entailed a form of reductionism in which “the self” –
the role of human psychology, our judgement, our attention and our will – was
sidestepped. Within this intellectual tradition there is only a short step,
from the understanding of the image as a representation of three-dimensional
space on a two-dimensional surface, to the idea of the image as a transparent
picture, a window towards the world. By taking this short step one would easily
lose sight of the role of the self in the practices
of making and viewing images.
In the second part the author
offers an alternative to the intellectual tradition described in the first
part. The idea of depiction as a neutral “view from nowhere” would support a
skeptical attitude towards communication, dialogue and human testimony, and
therefore our reliance upon each other and consequently our reliance on ourselves.
What was forgotten in this understanding of the image as a view from nowhere,
was that the image is an aid in the task cultivating our visual field, an aid
in sharing our views. Due to this
function of sharing, the image becomes a guide as we find our orientation in
this world. I might stand beside another person and see what she sees, but I do
not necessarily know her reading of it. The image adds a dimension to this
relation, since it does not only show me what the other sees. When an image
works properly it also shows how that
other person sees, and thus the image becomes an agent.
While the present thesis combines
the fields of philosophical epistemology, history of science and visual
studies, its main interest is philosophical. It engages with philosophical
misconceptions of depiction as a mimetic art form, of knowledge as
domestication and of perception as reception of data.
For the full text, see http://www.doria.fi/handle/10024/103039
¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨¨
Mari Lindman, Work
and Non-Work : On Work and Meaning (8 May, 2015)
Summary: It may seem self-evident that
employment is crucial to a happy life and that job creation is a central
societal concern. However, this dissertation suggests that work is neutralized
when it is understood simply as a valuable societal asset or as an individual
life project, while its existential, ethical and political significance in a
specific life situation is ignored. One example of such neutralization is when
the importance of work is reduced to the importance of “having a job”, whatever
its practical content or purposes. To challenge such neutralizations, the
author looks at the tension within the conceptions of work (necessity, hard
work and self-realization are three examples) which underlie them. The danger
of such neutralization is that political and existential worries about work and
the working life are swept under the rug. The book aims to repoliticize work by
looking at it as an essentially contested concept. The author suggests that
important aspects of work are revealed within such contestations of the role of
work in our lives and that tensions can be a fruitful point of departure for
resisting neutralizations of work. All chapters are structured around dialogues
with critical accounts of work, including those of Hannah Arendt, André Gorz,
Kathi Weeks, Simone Weil, Raimond Gaita, Karl Marx and Richard Sennett. What
does it mean to say that society has been invaded by necessity? What does it
mean to imagine a society beyond wage labor? Is it a utopia or a dystopia to
think about work as a limitless activity? What is at stake when work becomes a
commodity on the market? What are the hazards of fragmentation of work?
For the full text, see http://www.doria.fi/handle/10024/104317
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)