In the extensive discussion of the Gettier
cases (see my earlier entry), little attention has been given to the
notion of justification. If his critique is to have a point, Gettier needs the
justified-true-belief story. But how are we to understand the account that he is
attacking? When do we speak of justification, how does talk of justification
enter into the context of human conversation? Very often, the issue is
discussed as though matters of justification could be debated regardless of why
the question arises, who raises it, in what circumstances. (Contextualists are
an apparent exception – I hope to get back to them in a later entry.)
Gettier cites Ayer and Chisholm as expressing
a similar point by speaking in terms of “having a right to be sure” and “having
adequate evidence”, respectively. According to Gettier, these forms of
expression can be treated as equivalent.
Consider an example. Martha said, “The
water here is deep enough for diving in”. Was she justified in saying this? In
one case, our concern is with deciding whether or not we can jump in from here.
Here the question of justification is a question of reliability. Is what she’s
saying true? This is important, since if there are underwater rocks, diving in
would be very risky. We might ask her how she knows, though if she lives here
and we know she often goes swimming, we may just take her word for it,
provided, of course, we take her to be a reliable person. Either way we may tell
one another, “Martha knows the water here is deep enough for diving in”.
Would this be a case of knowledge equalling
justified true belief? Well, it would be strange here to speak about the latter
as a condition of knowledge. We don’t
infer Martha’s knowledge from the truth of what she is saying, rather we reason
to the truth from the conviction that she knows. So this doesn’t seem to be a
case of what Gettier is criticizing.
In another case, our concern is not with how
things stand, but with Martha’s right to say what she said. This is the most
likely to be the case when something goes wrong, but then that wouldn’t be the
sort of case Gettier was trying to exclude – no “true belief” there. On the
other hand we might think that what Martha said was true, but upbraid her for
giving her assurance too easily. Suppose she had asked a local whether diving
was safe there, and he had told her it was. Then it turned out he had been
speaking about a different shore with the same name. Though as it happens both
shores are safe. That’s seems more like a Gettier case. We might say she had an
excuse for making the mistake – she had a “justification” in that sense. But that
is hardly what Gettier was attacking: “knowledge = true belief with an excuse”.
(Neither would we say, with Chisholm, that her evidence was adequate, nor with
Ayer that she had a right to be sure.)
We haven’t succeeded, it seems, in finding
a case in which we are tempted to say what Gettier criticizes us for saying.
*
In the Gettier debate, there is little consideration
for how words are used in actual human conversation (how long will the anti-Wittgenstein,
anti-Ordinary Language Philosophy backlash last?). Consequently, what are evidently descriptions of different
contexts of use get treated as competing theories. Thus, according to Jonathan Jenkins Ichikawa & Matthias
Steup,
Internalists
about justification think that whether a belief is justified depends wholly on
states in some sense internal to the subject… Externalists about
justification think that factors external to the subject can be relevant for
justification…
(”TheAnalysis of Knowledge", Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), Edward N.
Zalta (ed.).)
Now, if what is at issue is a person’s responsibility for claiming to know something,
it is natural to assume that what will be relevant above all are “states
internal to” her, assuming that to mean: the information at her disposal, her
previous knowledge and experience, her competence for forming certain types of judgment,
etc., whereas when the reliability of
the speaker’s claim is concerned, matters independent of the speaker will
become important. Thus, rather than internalists and externalists addressing a single
question (what might that question be, in a context of regular conversation?), it
is plausible to suggest that what we have here are two fairly plausible answers
to two different questions.
In fact, neglect of conversation seems
almost to have become an ideology. In the article referred to above, speaking about
the context-dependence of knowledge-claims, Jonathan
Jenkins Ichikawa & Matthias Steup seem rather dismissive of the relevance
of considerations of use for the analysis of knowledge. According to them, the “relationship
between contextualism and the analysis of knowledge is not at all
straightforward. Arguably, they have different subject matters (the former a
word, and the latter a mental state)”, though they admit that “the methodology
of theorizing about knowledge may be helpfully informed by semantic
considerations about the language in which such theorizing takes place.” (Presumably, “semantic considerations” are
taken to include observations concerning the way a word enters into conversation.)
Getting clear about
the use of the word “know” (“semantics”), on their account, can thus be distinguished
from study of the “mental state” of knowing. Knowing, as it were, is like a
porcupine which can be observed, measured and dissected without our having to pay
much attention to the way the word “porcupine” figures in human conversation. What
is left open is how this language-independent observation of knowledge is
supposed to be carried out. I’m afraid that in practice it will simply consist
in the philosopher asking himself, independently of any context, “Would this be
knowledge?”, “Would that be knowledge?” , as it were, feeling the taste of the word
on his tongue. How reliable is that?
Dear Lars, with this
ReplyDelete–—I’m afraid that in practice it will simply consist in the philosopher asking himself, independently of any context, “Would this be knowledge?”, “Would that be knowledge?” , as it were, feeling the taste of the word on his tongue. How reliable is that?—
I'm afraid you've gone and hit the nail on the head. You're doing away with philosopher's intuitions here, and intuitions are their bread and butter. I should know, I've been practically flunked a few times for questioning them.
Thank you. I guess without faith in intuitions the whole project of analytic philosophy would need to be rethought.
ReplyDeleteYou may know that there's a good discussion of the idea of philosophical intuitions in Avner Baz's book, *When Words are Called for*, Chap. 3.
No, I didn't actually. I've just ordered it. Thank you. I do think the whole project for analytic (scientific) philosophy ought to be dropped though, on moral grounds, but that's me.
ReplyDeleteDear Lars, in case you missed it or thought I'd gone about ignoring you. I've replied to your comments on my post. All the best, JZ
ReplyDeleteI think there is a thing for traditional analytic philosophy to do without intuitions, but it is not a self-contained thing. (I always thought that in philosophy if your argument got whittled down to your own beliefs or intuitions you had lost, but that's not the way most of our colleagues roll.) Among the things we do talk about, discussions of "the logical problem of evil" in philosophy of religion, or some of the discussions you find in applied ethics, or perhaps the ship of Theseus in metaphysics, might be plausible cases. "Here are some propositions that (ordinary, non-philosophical) people seem to jointly hold; here is a proposed contradiction between them; what is the most plausible way to resolve the contradiction?"
ReplyDeleteThere are cases where I think that sort of thing can be valuable, because the assumption is already in place that people do believe the propositions in question, never mind why, and this sort of inquiry can help people think more sharply about why they believe what they believe and how their different beliefs relate to one another. But on the model presently under consideration the value doesn't come from defending or attacking any particular beliefs; just from considering the logical relationships between beliefs that people already have and different ways in which they might be reconciled.
Lars, this is a real world-ish example (I got it from Elliot Sober's "Core Questions" introductory text I think) that can be interesting to think about in relation to the Gettier cases. Let's say you are given a lottery ticket and say "I am going to lose the lottery." You believe it, you are very strongly statistically justified in your belief, and when the sun comes up tomorrow, lo and behold, you do not have a winning ticket.
Did you know you were going to lose? Some people would probably say yes. But I think I can at least understand the person who says, "well, not exactly, there was a chance that you could have won that you had no control over, however small."
My sense was that in many cases intuitions are not invoked in order to resolve a disagreement but in order to show that there is an issue there to disagree about. “Since people have the intuition that the ship of Theseus is the same (or they have the intuition that it is not the same, or some have one intuition that it is and some that it isn’t), the QUESTION whether it is the same ship (although one by one all the planks have been exchanged for new ones over the years) is a real question. Since we are eager to reply even if there is no context, the question must mean something independently of context.” The thing is there, like the porcupine. In other words, it does not matter to some philosophers which intuition is right, only that we have intuitions (that we are willing to pronounce), hence that there is something to BE right or wrong about.
ReplyDeleteIn a similar spirit the Law of the Excluded Middle is often invoked: “the ship must either be the same or not”, “you must either know or not know that you’re not going to win.”
Of this I am suspicious. And accordingly, too, I am hesitant whether in discussing these claims and counter-claims we are really investigating beliefs people hold. Isn’t language just idling here?
“I know I’m not going to win” sounds to me like someone wanting to make sure we don’t suspect her of ungrounded optimism. (If she did win, would we say she was “wrong”?) Or else she is trying to tell us she has special information.